Hide table of contents

Imagine a widescreen oil painting from the Romantic era, depicting a bridge that serves as a boundary between two vastly different realms. On one side, the bridge begins in a realm of pure forms, where abstract geometry, forcefields, neon glass, and fractals dominate the landscape, creating an ethereal and surreal atmosphere. This side is characterized by its vibrant colors, glowing elements, and a sense of otherworldly beauty. The bridge itself is an architectural marvel, with no support pillars, appearing to float effortlessly. As it spans across, it transitions into the Roman Empire, where the environment shifts dramatically to a more down-to-earth setting. Here, the landscape is adorned with marble structures, classical Roman architecture, and lacks any form of abstract geometry. The bridge seamlessly blends these two contrasting worlds, symbolizing a connection between the mystical and the tangible. The overall scene is depicted with the lush, dramatic lighting and emotional depth characteristic of Romantic era oil paintings, capturing the viewer's imagination and inviting them to ponder the bridge's symbolic passage between the abstract and the concrete. The painting's wide format enhances the grandeur of the scene, emphasizing the vast distance the bridge covers and the profound impact of its existence.

 

I have been a practising Stoic for over 10 years. I adopted Stoicism before I encountered the sequences and LessWrong-style rationalism. To me, Stoicism and rationalism serve complementary purposes, tackling different aspects of life.

Rationalism, to me, is related to getting a better understanding of the world, and how the mind functions. It’s generally descriptive, attempting to make models that accurately describe aspects of existence.

Stoicism, to me, is all about the nitty-gritty aspects of self-improvement. 
It’s more about instruction than explanation, featuring perspectives and explanations that are conducive to embodying a set of character traits commonly referred to as “virtues”.

This post will start by analysing utilitarianism, the most common ethical approach among rationalists, followed by a pragmatic integration of utilitarianism, Stoicism, and rationality.

But first, a bit of background.

 

Stoicism vs Utilitarianism

Stoicism is a type of Virtue Ethics, focused on the workings of your cognition — an action is “good” if it develops a set of desirable character traits (virtues). A bad action, on the contrary, is an action that builds bad habits (vices). In this view, committing genocide is bad because you don’t want to train yourself to be a person who commits genocide.

Consequentialism is all about the consequences of your actions — an action is “good” if its positive consequences outweigh its negative consequences. An action is bad if the downsides outweigh the upsides. In this view, committing genocide is bad because you cause a lot of suffering to a lot of people, robbing their agency by killing them, and causing a bunch of negative secondary effects.

At first glance, these are two very different ways of looking at ethics. Stoicism is sometimes presented as incompatible with utilitarianism. Let’s illustrate this gap through a story I heard from a friend. My friend attended an ethics course at university, and told me about his professor’s view of virtue ethics (paraphrased):

“Utilitarianism is about looking at the result of actions and judging the outcome. Virtue ethics is about acting like a ‘good person’, whatever that means!”

Arguing for the superiority of one view over the other misses the point. Why argue about “who is right”, when you can aim for an integration, getting the upsides from both views? Let’s move on to a pragmatic integration!

 

The Implicit Virtue of Utilitarianism

You are an expert utilitarian. You have trained your predictive capacities, turning yourself into a superforecaster, able to accurately model the outcomes of most decisions you make. You have decided on how you want to aggregate values, how you want to weigh negative vs positive outcomes, researched population ethics and done due diligence on all the relevant desiderata.

Your ability to weigh courses of action is unsurpassed amongst your kin.

QED? Not really.

Knowing the right course of action is meaningless if you don’t act on your knowledge. Without action, utilitarianism is nothing but a reduction of real-world issues into ivory-tower logic puzzles.

Utilitarianism carries an implicit virtue — acting to make the most good happen. The implicit virtue of utilitarianism is out of scope for consequentialist ethical reasoning. Utilitarianism can tell you that it is a good idea to become such a person (high expected value), but it doesn’t give you a roadmap for how to get there.

Knowing what to do without being able to get to it is all too common. I think of this as the intention-action gap. Let’s see what we need to add to the mix if we want to get something going.

 

Some Complimentary Virtues

We start with the implicit virtue of utilitarianism — being a person who acts to make the most good happen. This virtue is about having a direction/target, a sense of how we want things to be. For reasons that will be obvious soon, let’s call this virtue Justice.

Besides embodying Justice, we need to know a lot of things about the world and ourselves. If we don’t, we risk fucking up our expected value calculations. We need knowledge of the world if we want to act in it. We need knowledge of ourselves to work on motivation, biased thinking, and hang-ups that block our way. This is the domain of LessWrong-style rationality practice. Let’s call this virtue Wisdom.

Besides Wisdom, we need a bit of oomph. We need to be able to commit and push ahead, acting according to our ethics even if it’s uncomfortable, dangerous or awkward. We need to cultivate a “go get them”-attitude, a primal energy that helps us get shit going, make a move, and enjoy action. Let’s call this virtue Courage.

Besides Courage, we need to be able to resist temptations. Eradicating malaria is tempting, but so is netflix and chocolate. We can force ourselves to go against our immediate preferences by shaming and “shoulding” ourselves into the right course of action. This is likely to backfire, causing friction and wasting processing cycles on inner conflict. A better approach is to reprogram our desire/aversion responses so that we desire good things, and feel aversion towards things that distract us. The Greeks had a nice word for this virtue, calling it Sophrosyne.

 

Stumbling Upon Stoicism

The virtues presented in the last section are the traditional Stoic virtues. You can reshape your cognition to embody these virtues through Stoic practice. Stoicism has inspired great people throughout history to achieve their goals. One of the main Stoic Philosophers had a side-gig as Roman Emperor.

There is much material written on Stoicism, both primary materials and derivative takes. There are mental models, practices and techniques, mindsets and frameworks. Reading Epiktetos’ Enchiridion changed my life. He is a grumpy/prude old guy, but I can heartily recommend him anyway.

Stoicism is all about cultivating virtue, integrating thoughts, emotions, value judgements and actions into a better-functioning cognitive machinery. The virtues all tie into each other, forming a coherent system focused on navigating life with skill and grace.

Cognitive Behavioural Therapy is inspired by/derived from Stoicism. It has been the dominant therapeutic modality for a long time at this point.

 

Paradoxical Perspective Shifts

Stoic practice involves a reframing of experience that shifts your “ethical focus”. When engaging in Stoic practice, you stop putting moral weight on the consequences of your actions. Instead, you shift the moral weight to being a person who acts virtuously.

This is a paradoxical stance, captured perfectly in a classic Stoic maxim:

“1. Virtue is the sole good” - Paradoxa Stoicorum by Cicero

This outlook is paradoxical because Justice usually involves things that are external to your cognition. If you base Justice on utilitarianism, you put moral weight on acting according to utilitarian expected value calculations.

Stated simply, the paradox is:

  • Focus not on the world, but only on becoming a good person.
  • Part of being a good person is wanting to do good in the world.

Personally, I resolve this paradox by treating “Virtue is the sole good” as an invitation to shift my focus. My cognition, my actions and their consequences form a system. It’s natural to focus on the action/consequence part of this system. Stoicism invites us to shift our attention “upstream”, focusing on the cognition/action part of this system.

This ethical perspective shift highlights the role of our conditioning in the outcomes of our actions. Shifting ethical considerations to target the state of your own cognition is a key stoic practice.

This perspective shift doesn’t mean that you grow apart from the world, far from it! Since the early days, Stoics have been engaged with society, working to make the world a better place. Stoicism emphasizes action aligned with Justice.

 

Summary

In this post, I’ve shown how Utilitarianism, with its focus on what to do, needs a complementary answer to how we go about the actual “doing”. I’ve shown how Stoicism is one such answer, deriving the Stoic virtues out of utilitarianism’s implicit commitment to action.

Here are some resources for getting into Stoicism:

Comments


No comments on this post yet.
Be the first to respond.
Curated and popular this week
Paul Present
 ·  · 28m read
 · 
Note: I am not a malaria expert. This is my best-faith attempt at answering a question that was bothering me, but this field is a large and complex field, and I’ve almost certainly misunderstood something somewhere along the way. Summary While the world made incredible progress in reducing malaria cases from 2000 to 2015, the past 10 years have seen malaria cases stop declining and start rising. I investigated potential reasons behind this increase through reading the existing literature and looking at publicly available data, and I identified three key factors explaining the rise: 1. Population Growth: Africa's population has increased by approximately 75% since 2000. This alone explains most of the increase in absolute case numbers, while cases per capita have remained relatively flat since 2015. 2. Stagnant Funding: After rapid growth starting in 2000, funding for malaria prevention plateaued around 2010. 3. Insecticide Resistance: Mosquitoes have become increasingly resistant to the insecticides used in bednets over the past 20 years. This has made older models of bednets less effective, although they still have some effect. Newer models of bednets developed in response to insecticide resistance are more effective but still not widely deployed.  I very crudely estimate that without any of these factors, there would be 55% fewer malaria cases in the world than what we see today. I think all three of these factors are roughly equally important in explaining the difference.  Alternative explanations like removal of PFAS, climate change, or invasive mosquito species don't appear to be major contributors.  Overall this investigation made me more convinced that bednets are an effective global health intervention.  Introduction In 2015, malaria rates were down, and EAs were celebrating. Giving What We Can posted this incredible gif showing the decrease in malaria cases across Africa since 2000: Giving What We Can said that > The reduction in malaria has be
Rory Fenton
 ·  · 6m read
 · 
Cross-posted from my blog. Contrary to my carefully crafted brand as a weak nerd, I go to a local CrossFit gym a few times a week. Every year, the gym raises funds for a scholarship for teens from lower-income families to attend their summer camp program. I don’t know how many Crossfit-interested low-income teens there are in my small town, but I’ll guess there are perhaps 2 of them who would benefit from the scholarship. After all, CrossFit is pretty niche, and the town is small. Helping youngsters get swole in the Pacific Northwest is not exactly as cost-effective as preventing malaria in Malawi. But I notice I feel drawn to supporting the scholarship anyway. Every time it pops in my head I think, “My money could fully solve this problem”. The camp only costs a few hundred dollars per kid and if there are just 2 kids who need support, I could give $500 and there would no longer be teenagers in my town who want to go to a CrossFit summer camp but can’t. Thanks to me, the hero, this problem would be entirely solved. 100%. That is not how most nonprofit work feels to me. You are only ever making small dents in important problems I want to work on big problems. Global poverty. Malaria. Everyone not suddenly dying. But if I’m honest, what I really want is to solve those problems. Me, personally, solve them. This is a continued source of frustration and sadness because I absolutely cannot solve those problems. Consider what else my $500 CrossFit scholarship might do: * I want to save lives, and USAID suddenly stops giving $7 billion a year to PEPFAR. So I give $500 to the Rapid Response Fund. My donation solves 0.000001% of the problem and I feel like I have failed. * I want to solve climate change, and getting to net zero will require stopping or removing emissions of 1,500 billion tons of carbon dioxide. I give $500 to a policy nonprofit that reduces emissions, in expectation, by 50 tons. My donation solves 0.000000003% of the problem and I feel like I have f
LewisBollard
 ·  · 8m read
 · 
> How the dismal science can help us end the dismal treatment of farm animals By Martin Gould ---------------------------------------- Note: This post was crossposted from the Open Philanthropy Farm Animal Welfare Research Newsletter by the Forum team, with the author's permission. The author may not see or respond to comments on this post. ---------------------------------------- This year we’ll be sharing a few notes from my colleagues on their areas of expertise. The first is from Martin. I’ll be back next month. - Lewis In 2024, Denmark announced plans to introduce the world’s first carbon tax on cow, sheep, and pig farming. Climate advocates celebrated, but animal advocates should be much more cautious. When Denmark’s Aarhus municipality tested a similar tax in 2022, beef purchases dropped by 40% while demand for chicken and pork increased. Beef is the most emissions-intensive meat, so carbon taxes hit it hardest — and Denmark’s policies don’t even cover chicken or fish. When the price of beef rises, consumers mostly shift to other meats like chicken. And replacing beef with chicken means more animals suffer in worse conditions — about 190 chickens are needed to match the meat from one cow, and chickens are raised in much worse conditions. It may be possible to design carbon taxes which avoid this outcome; a recent paper argues that a broad carbon tax would reduce all meat production (although it omits impacts on egg or dairy production). But with cows ten times more emissions-intensive than chicken per kilogram of meat, other governments may follow Denmark’s lead — focusing taxes on the highest emitters while ignoring the welfare implications. Beef is easily the most emissions-intensive meat, but also requires the fewest animals for a given amount. The graph shows climate emissions per tonne of meat on the right-hand side, and the number of animals needed to produce a kilogram of meat on the left. The fish “lives lost” number varies significantly by