Hide table of contents

Previously: Epistemic Hell

-- 

The Journal of Controversial Ideas was founded in 2021 by Francesca Minerva, Jeff Mcmahan, and Peter Singer so that low-rent philosophers could publish articles in defense of black-face Halloween costumes, animal rights terrorism, and having sex with animals. I, for one, am appalled. The JoCI and its cute little articles are far too tame; we simply must do better.

And so I propose The Journal of Dangerous Ideas (the JoDI). I suppose it doesn’t go without saying in this case, but I believe that the creation of such a journal, and the call to thought which it represents, will be to the benefit of all mankind.

What is a dangerous idea?

an idea whose birthing harms the world; an idea whose existence represents a threat to person or creature (to the good ones, not the bad ones which should be threatened); an idea which possesses the quality of being dangerous (like hardcore pornography, “you know it when you see it”).

I reckon there are many ways in which an idea can be dangerous: technologically dangerous of course, but also scientifically dangerous, philosophically dangerous, socially dangerous, artistically dangerous, spiritually dangerous, and so on and so forth.

Some Examples

Black Balls

 

One way of looking at human creativity is as a process of pulling balls out of a giant urn. The balls represent possible ideas, discoveries, technological inventions. Over the course of history, we have extracted a great many balls— mostly white (beneficial) but also various shades of gray (moderately harmful ones and mixed blessings). The cumulative effect on the human condition has so far been overwhelmingly positive, and may be much better still in the future.

What we haven’t extracted, so far, is a black ball: a technology that invariably or by default destroys the civilization that invents it. The reason is not that we have been particularly careful or wise in our technology policy. We have just been lucky.

—Nick Bostrom, “The Vulnerable World Hypothesis

Let’s borrow Bostrom’s scheme and adapt it as so:

Light balls

  • White balls—beneficial ideas
  • Light grey balls—mixed blessing (dual-use) ideas

Dark balls

  • Dark grey balls—moderately harmful (e.g. a new scamming method)
  • Black balls—truly pernicious species-altering or -ending ideas (Bostrom gives the example of “easy nukes” in his paper: suppose it became relatively trivial and cheap for a small group of adults to build a nuclear bomb)

There are two primary questions then:

  • Would the JoDI increase the overall amount of harm done from dark balls?
  • Would the JoDI increase the total benefit from drawing white balls enough to offset any increased levels of harm from dark balls?

In regards to the first question, it seems likely that the JoDI would, simply by virtue of its existence, inspire us to grab more dark balls from the urn. But for these balls to cause harm, they must “fall into the wrong hands”, so to speak. It seems plausible to that the JoDI could cause a drop in the rate of dark balls grabbed or possessed by bad actors because more good actors will be reaching for dark balls (assuming large numbers of people are aware of the JoDI and attempting to publish in it). While too much oversight defeats the entire purpose of the journal, it might make sense to have some kind of initial screening process whereby sufficiently dangerous black balls can be kept under wraps and routed to the appropriate authorities/experts. This screening process presents its own serious concerns and questions (who watches the watchers?), but it should still increase the chances that a black ball is pulled in the safest possible manner. For lighter and less dangerous orbs, publication can obviate the idea’s element of surprise and give us a head start on developing new safety or security technologies, regulations, counter-arguments, cultural movements, etc.

White Balls

H. P. Lovecraft, writing to Edwin Baird, the first editor of Weird Tales:

Popular authors do not and apparently cannot appreciate the fact that true art is obtainable only by rejecting normality and conventionality in toto, and approaching a theme purged utterly of any usual or preconceived point of view. Wild and “different” as they may consider their quasi-weird products, it remains a fact that the bizarrerie is on the surface alone; and that basically they reiterate the same old conventional values and motives and perspectives. Good and evil, teleological illusion, sugary sentiment, anthropocentric psychology—the usual superficial stock in trade, and all shot through with the eternal and inescapable commonplace….

Whoever wrote a story from the point of view that man is a blemish on the cosmos, who ought to be eradicated? As an example—a young man I know lately told me that he means to write a story about a scientist who wishes to dominate the earth, and who to accomplish his ends trains and overdevelops germs…and leads armies of them in the manner of the Egyptian plagues. I told him that although this theme has promise, it is made utterly commonplace by assigning the scientist a normal motive. There is nothing outré about wanting to conquer the earth; Alexander, Napoleon, and Wilhelm II wanted to do that. Instead, I told my friend, he should conceive a man with a morbid, frantic, shuddering hatred of the life-principle itself, who wishes to extirpate from the planet every trace of biological organism, animal and vegetable alike, including himself. That would be tolerably original. But after all, originality lies with the author. One can’t write a weird story of real power without perfect psychological detachment from the human scene, and a magic prism of imagination which suffuses theme and style alike with that grotesquerie and disquieting distortion characteristic of morbid vision. Only a cynic can create horror—for behind every masterpiece of the sort must reside a driving demonic force that despises the human race and its illusions, and longs to pull them to pieces and mock them.

Lovecraft’s argument for the novelty of a truly pessimistic perspective also applies to the general pursuit of ideas: all of human thought and activity is tilted towards goodness—towards pleasure, happiness, flourishing, sunshine, rainbows, kittens; we rarely, if ever, gaze into the abyss in a sustained and systematic manner; the black forests and swamps of the landscape of ideas are under-explored; we sometimes stumble upon detrimental ideas in the happy valleys and sunny meadows of idea-land, so it would stand to reason that we might also stumble upon the most wondrous and beneficent ideas while exploring darker terrain; if “the road to hell is paved with good intentions”, then ipso facto the road to heaven is paved with bad intentions; QED.

ALL THE BALLS

Is The Journal of Dangerous Ideas a bad idea? Yeah, probably.

But we can’t know for sure. And what I do know for sure is that we didn’t get this far by playing it safe or playing scared.

We got this far by playing to WIN. We got this far by putting all of our SKIN IN THE GAME and playing for KEEPS. We got this far by going BALLS TO THE WALL and putting the PEDAL TO THE METAL.

So how do we want to go out?

Do we want to timidly grope around for white balls until we accidentally (but inevitably) grab a black ball? Or do we want to reach for ALL THE BALLS and go out in a BLAZE OF GLORY with our guns BLAZING?

Do we want to slowly fade away or rage against the dying of the light?

Do we want to go out like cowards or go wildly into that good night?

 

(To answer the obvious question: No, I do not have any current plans to actually found the JoDI, so if anyone is feeling sufficiently inspired, then by all means go for it. I’m happy to consult on the project and share the lessons I’ve learned from founding Seeds of Science.)

Further reading

And two from me:

Comments1


Sorted by Click to highlight new comments since:

I'm not sure if this is a good post (I didn't vote on it either way), but it seems like the sort of thing that would be far more likely to get a positive reception on April Fools Day than any other point.

Curated and popular this week
Paul Present
 ·  · 28m read
 · 
Note: I am not a malaria expert. This is my best-faith attempt at answering a question that was bothering me, but this field is a large and complex field, and I’ve almost certainly misunderstood something somewhere along the way. Summary While the world made incredible progress in reducing malaria cases from 2000 to 2015, the past 10 years have seen malaria cases stop declining and start rising. I investigated potential reasons behind this increase through reading the existing literature and looking at publicly available data, and I identified three key factors explaining the rise: 1. Population Growth: Africa's population has increased by approximately 75% since 2000. This alone explains most of the increase in absolute case numbers, while cases per capita have remained relatively flat since 2015. 2. Stagnant Funding: After rapid growth starting in 2000, funding for malaria prevention plateaued around 2010. 3. Insecticide Resistance: Mosquitoes have become increasingly resistant to the insecticides used in bednets over the past 20 years. This has made older models of bednets less effective, although they still have some effect. Newer models of bednets developed in response to insecticide resistance are more effective but still not widely deployed.  I very crudely estimate that without any of these factors, there would be 55% fewer malaria cases in the world than what we see today. I think all three of these factors are roughly equally important in explaining the difference.  Alternative explanations like removal of PFAS, climate change, or invasive mosquito species don't appear to be major contributors.  Overall this investigation made me more convinced that bednets are an effective global health intervention.  Introduction In 2015, malaria rates were down, and EAs were celebrating. Giving What We Can posted this incredible gif showing the decrease in malaria cases across Africa since 2000: Giving What We Can said that > The reduction in malaria has be
Rory Fenton
 ·  · 6m read
 · 
Cross-posted from my blog. Contrary to my carefully crafted brand as a weak nerd, I go to a local CrossFit gym a few times a week. Every year, the gym raises funds for a scholarship for teens from lower-income families to attend their summer camp program. I don’t know how many Crossfit-interested low-income teens there are in my small town, but I’ll guess there are perhaps 2 of them who would benefit from the scholarship. After all, CrossFit is pretty niche, and the town is small. Helping youngsters get swole in the Pacific Northwest is not exactly as cost-effective as preventing malaria in Malawi. But I notice I feel drawn to supporting the scholarship anyway. Every time it pops in my head I think, “My money could fully solve this problem”. The camp only costs a few hundred dollars per kid and if there are just 2 kids who need support, I could give $500 and there would no longer be teenagers in my town who want to go to a CrossFit summer camp but can’t. Thanks to me, the hero, this problem would be entirely solved. 100%. That is not how most nonprofit work feels to me. You are only ever making small dents in important problems I want to work on big problems. Global poverty. Malaria. Everyone not suddenly dying. But if I’m honest, what I really want is to solve those problems. Me, personally, solve them. This is a continued source of frustration and sadness because I absolutely cannot solve those problems. Consider what else my $500 CrossFit scholarship might do: * I want to save lives, and USAID suddenly stops giving $7 billion a year to PEPFAR. So I give $500 to the Rapid Response Fund. My donation solves 0.000001% of the problem and I feel like I have failed. * I want to solve climate change, and getting to net zero will require stopping or removing emissions of 1,500 billion tons of carbon dioxide. I give $500 to a policy nonprofit that reduces emissions, in expectation, by 50 tons. My donation solves 0.000000003% of the problem and I feel like I have f
LewisBollard
 ·  · 8m read
 · 
> How the dismal science can help us end the dismal treatment of farm animals By Martin Gould ---------------------------------------- Note: This post was crossposted from the Open Philanthropy Farm Animal Welfare Research Newsletter by the Forum team, with the author's permission. The author may not see or respond to comments on this post. ---------------------------------------- This year we’ll be sharing a few notes from my colleagues on their areas of expertise. The first is from Martin. I’ll be back next month. - Lewis In 2024, Denmark announced plans to introduce the world’s first carbon tax on cow, sheep, and pig farming. Climate advocates celebrated, but animal advocates should be much more cautious. When Denmark’s Aarhus municipality tested a similar tax in 2022, beef purchases dropped by 40% while demand for chicken and pork increased. Beef is the most emissions-intensive meat, so carbon taxes hit it hardest — and Denmark’s policies don’t even cover chicken or fish. When the price of beef rises, consumers mostly shift to other meats like chicken. And replacing beef with chicken means more animals suffer in worse conditions — about 190 chickens are needed to match the meat from one cow, and chickens are raised in much worse conditions. It may be possible to design carbon taxes which avoid this outcome; a recent paper argues that a broad carbon tax would reduce all meat production (although it omits impacts on egg or dairy production). But with cows ten times more emissions-intensive than chicken per kilogram of meat, other governments may follow Denmark’s lead — focusing taxes on the highest emitters while ignoring the welfare implications. Beef is easily the most emissions-intensive meat, but also requires the fewest animals for a given amount. The graph shows climate emissions per tonne of meat on the right-hand side, and the number of animals needed to produce a kilogram of meat on the left. The fish “lives lost” number varies significantly by