I previously asked whether Longtermism entails that we should prepare what I call a biotic hedge, in case we should fail to prevent existential catastrophe. I received some very helpful feedback. Here is the original question: https://forum.effectivealtruism.org/posts/FvfJSkJYNZwRYL6XD/does-utilitarian-longtermism-imply-directed-panspermia

The biotic hedge refers to directed panspermia, which is where we intentionally send out the seeds of life to other planets or moons around the galaxy. This is to hedge against the possibility that all life on earth is wiped out. We know that in 4 billion years the sun will expand and engulf earth, which would constitute such an event.

Longtermisn is the view that we should evaluate our actions based on how they will affect future beings, not just present beings.

A common objection to directed panspermia is that it constitutes an irreversible, possibly harmful action (in a epistemic sense), which should be avoided if possible.

Consider a few trolley problems. They take place in Trolleyville, where it’s a possibility that persons are tied to tracks, but that’s all you know. Assessing the probability of this is a challenge.

Tunnel and Wall 1. A trolley is careening toward a wall. Five people are tied to the wall. A second track diverts into a tunnel, which you cannot see into. You have the option to pull a switch and divert the trolley into the tunnel. The trolley will surely kill the people if it hits them and the wall. Who knows what might happen in the tunnel. This is Trolleyville, after all. Should you pull the switch?

It seems obvious to me that you should.

Tunnel and Wall 2. Now suppose the same tunnel and wall setup, but instead the five people are on the trolley. Should you pull the switch?

Again, it seems like you should, even though this is Trolleyville.

Tunnel and Wall 3. Again, we have the same tunnel and wall setup, but this time we have only possible future persons on the trolley (fertilized embryos, maybe). If they hit the wall, they will never come to exist. If they go in the tunnel, they might.

In all cases, we take irreversible, potentially harmful action to save some morally relevant persons. Cases 1 and 2 suffice to show that these conditions are not enough to make action impermissible.

Clearly I must defend case 3 a bit. I do not expect the same intuitive support. But I do think that it is morally congruent in relevant ways.

First, I draw on the longtermist claim that future persons matter morally, and this mattering is not discounted by time, like money is. One future person matters morally just as much as one presently existing person.

The moral value of actions that affect them may be discounted by epistemic considerations, like by the probability that an action has a particular effect on them. But not by time alone.

These possible persons also need not be humans. I draw on standard claims about speciesism, that humans are not the only beings that matter morally. I think the case is morally the same whether the possible future persons are humans or not.

So just as in cases 1 and 2, if in case 3 we pull the switch, we send a trolley careening down a tunnel. We don’t know if any people or morally relevant beings are on the tunnel track in any case. We have to work with the information we have. In cases 1 and 2, it seems like the information we have requires us to pull the switch. But there is no moral difference in case 3. So even without the intuition, it seems we must still pull the switch.

I can map these three cases to some more concrete existential risk examples, which I will now do.

Case 1 is an asteroid. A big one. It would wipe out all life on earth. If possible, we should divert the asteroid. We are not sure if it will hit and destroy some other morally relevant life elsewhere in the universe. But we should divert it anyway.

Case 2 is human spacefaring. If we can achieve this, we should, because it saves humanity from certain doom on Earth due to the expansion of the Sun.

Case 3 is directed panspermia. If we don’t do it, we ensure that future persons in the Earth-originated tree of life get engulfed by the Sun, while sending Earth-originated life to the universe saves it from this fate.

The ignorance about what might be in the tunnel does not absolve us of the responsibility of saving morally relevant beings from a certain doom. It shouldn’t absolve us of the responsibility to preserve future persons obtainable by directed panspermia.

I believe I can strengthen the intuition a bit if I appeal to some conceivable scientific advances that might arrive soon. Namely, it may be possible to develop biological material that can be stored on a ship, and when it comes into contact with habitable environments, it develops into human beings just as a zygote does. It should be intuitive that if we could do this, it would be permissible, given longtermist values. There is no distinction between these humans and those send spacefaring on a ship, other than the social discontinuity of birth.

But if we are to avoid the accusation of speciesism, we should be willing to send other such biological material that will develop into other morally relevant beings. I contend that this is directed panspermia. It seems reasonable to claim that eventually morally relevant beings will evolve, if not full nonhuman persons, from appropriately selected biological samples.

Consider two more cases.

Tunnel and Wall 4. Five people, including you, are in a trolley careening toward a wall. In front of the tunnel, tied on the track, is one person. Is it permissible for you to pull the switch inside the trolley to veer into the tunnel, killing the one who is tied up, but saving the five in the trolley?

Tunnel and Wall 5. Five people, including you, are on a trolley careening toward a wall. You can pull a switch and divert into a tunnel. As far as you can see, nothing is tied to the track, but this is Trolleyville.

The analogous existential risk cases might be as follows. For case 4, an asteroid is heading toward Earth. Suppose we can save ourselves only by diverting it into Europa, and suppose we know it has life. Case 5 is like this, but we do not know if life is on Europa.

Between cases 4 and 5, 5 is clearly less morally troubling. I think case 4 is such that pulling the switch is morally permissible. But then case 5 is morally permissible. From a moral, longtermist perspective, 5 is nearly identical to case 3. The only difference is that you and four others are on the trolley in 5, while in 3 the trolley has possible future persons. According to longtermism, this is not a morally relevant difference. Case 5 seems permissible, if not obligatory. So case 3 should be permissible too, if not obligatory. Thus, given what we now know, it seems permissible to plan for and engage in directed panspermia, to ensure that possible future persons can exist beyond the expansion of the Sun.

This has implications for how we approach space exploration. Careful sterilization of spacecraft and instruments makes sense from a scientific perspective, where we do not want to contaminate the environment in which we are trying to make discoveries. But the moral case for avoiding panspermia is less strong, especially when we do not know one way or the other whether life exists elsewhere. And even in some cases, it may be permissible to engage in directed panspermia if the risk to Earth’s tree of life is great enough, even if there is reason to believe some primitive life exists on a target system.

Comments1


Sorted by Click to highlight new comments since:

Executive summary: The post argues that longtermism, the view that the effects of our actions on future beings have significant moral weight, provides a case for engaging in directed panspermia to preserve life from existential threats.

Key points:

  1. Longtermism implies future beings, including nonhuman or potential future beings, have moral worth akin to present beings.
  2. Actions that irreversibly affect future beings may be permissible if they mitigate existential threats, even if outcomes are uncertain.
  3. Directed panspermia to spread life mitigates existential risks like the Sun engulfing Earth, so is permissible by longtermism.
  4. Advancing technology may enable creating and preserving more sophisticated life via panspermia.
  5. These arguments suggest more permissive approaches to panspermia in space exploration to protect future beings.

 

 

This comment was auto-generated by the EA Forum Team. Feel free to point out issues with this summary by replying to the comment, and contact us if you have feedback.

Curated and popular this week
Paul Present
 ·  · 28m read
 · 
Note: I am not a malaria expert. This is my best-faith attempt at answering a question that was bothering me, but this field is a large and complex field, and I’ve almost certainly misunderstood something somewhere along the way. Summary While the world made incredible progress in reducing malaria cases from 2000 to 2015, the past 10 years have seen malaria cases stop declining and start rising. I investigated potential reasons behind this increase through reading the existing literature and looking at publicly available data, and I identified three key factors explaining the rise: 1. Population Growth: Africa's population has increased by approximately 75% since 2000. This alone explains most of the increase in absolute case numbers, while cases per capita have remained relatively flat since 2015. 2. Stagnant Funding: After rapid growth starting in 2000, funding for malaria prevention plateaued around 2010. 3. Insecticide Resistance: Mosquitoes have become increasingly resistant to the insecticides used in bednets over the past 20 years. This has made older models of bednets less effective, although they still have some effect. Newer models of bednets developed in response to insecticide resistance are more effective but still not widely deployed.  I very crudely estimate that without any of these factors, there would be 55% fewer malaria cases in the world than what we see today. I think all three of these factors are roughly equally important in explaining the difference.  Alternative explanations like removal of PFAS, climate change, or invasive mosquito species don't appear to be major contributors.  Overall this investigation made me more convinced that bednets are an effective global health intervention.  Introduction In 2015, malaria rates were down, and EAs were celebrating. Giving What We Can posted this incredible gif showing the decrease in malaria cases across Africa since 2000: Giving What We Can said that > The reduction in malaria has be
Rory Fenton
 ·  · 6m read
 · 
Cross-posted from my blog. Contrary to my carefully crafted brand as a weak nerd, I go to a local CrossFit gym a few times a week. Every year, the gym raises funds for a scholarship for teens from lower-income families to attend their summer camp program. I don’t know how many Crossfit-interested low-income teens there are in my small town, but I’ll guess there are perhaps 2 of them who would benefit from the scholarship. After all, CrossFit is pretty niche, and the town is small. Helping youngsters get swole in the Pacific Northwest is not exactly as cost-effective as preventing malaria in Malawi. But I notice I feel drawn to supporting the scholarship anyway. Every time it pops in my head I think, “My money could fully solve this problem”. The camp only costs a few hundred dollars per kid and if there are just 2 kids who need support, I could give $500 and there would no longer be teenagers in my town who want to go to a CrossFit summer camp but can’t. Thanks to me, the hero, this problem would be entirely solved. 100%. That is not how most nonprofit work feels to me. You are only ever making small dents in important problems I want to work on big problems. Global poverty. Malaria. Everyone not suddenly dying. But if I’m honest, what I really want is to solve those problems. Me, personally, solve them. This is a continued source of frustration and sadness because I absolutely cannot solve those problems. Consider what else my $500 CrossFit scholarship might do: * I want to save lives, and USAID suddenly stops giving $7 billion a year to PEPFAR. So I give $500 to the Rapid Response Fund. My donation solves 0.000001% of the problem and I feel like I have failed. * I want to solve climate change, and getting to net zero will require stopping or removing emissions of 1,500 billion tons of carbon dioxide. I give $500 to a policy nonprofit that reduces emissions, in expectation, by 50 tons. My donation solves 0.000000003% of the problem and I feel like I have f
LewisBollard
 ·  · 8m read
 · 
> How the dismal science can help us end the dismal treatment of farm animals By Martin Gould ---------------------------------------- Note: This post was crossposted from the Open Philanthropy Farm Animal Welfare Research Newsletter by the Forum team, with the author's permission. The author may not see or respond to comments on this post. ---------------------------------------- This year we’ll be sharing a few notes from my colleagues on their areas of expertise. The first is from Martin. I’ll be back next month. - Lewis In 2024, Denmark announced plans to introduce the world’s first carbon tax on cow, sheep, and pig farming. Climate advocates celebrated, but animal advocates should be much more cautious. When Denmark’s Aarhus municipality tested a similar tax in 2022, beef purchases dropped by 40% while demand for chicken and pork increased. Beef is the most emissions-intensive meat, so carbon taxes hit it hardest — and Denmark’s policies don’t even cover chicken or fish. When the price of beef rises, consumers mostly shift to other meats like chicken. And replacing beef with chicken means more animals suffer in worse conditions — about 190 chickens are needed to match the meat from one cow, and chickens are raised in much worse conditions. It may be possible to design carbon taxes which avoid this outcome; a recent paper argues that a broad carbon tax would reduce all meat production (although it omits impacts on egg or dairy production). But with cows ten times more emissions-intensive than chicken per kilogram of meat, other governments may follow Denmark’s lead — focusing taxes on the highest emitters while ignoring the welfare implications. Beef is easily the most emissions-intensive meat, but also requires the fewest animals for a given amount. The graph shows climate emissions per tonne of meat on the right-hand side, and the number of animals needed to produce a kilogram of meat on the left. The fish “lives lost” number varies significantly by