“Expected Value Altruism” might be a less catchy name than Effective Altruism, but it would be a more precise and less antagonizing name for a movement whose most distinguishing characteristic is not effectiveness broadly, but an expected-value-calculating approach to making the world better.

Most people want to be effective at achieving their goals, even if these are to help others. So, it doesn’t seem a self-proclaimed interest in effectiveness is what divides EAs from altruistic non-EAs. Part of the divide could be over how much emphasis to place on effectiveness, but there are altruists who are very interested in effectiveness and impact but do not identify as EAs. The most apparent general disagreement between them and EAs would be, I think, over the methods for determining what altruistic actions to take. EAs and EA orgs claim to use expected value methodology occasionally or often to determine the course of their altruism, while non-EAs and non-EA orgs either do not use these at all, or put much less emphasis on them. If this is what primarily distinguishes EAs from non-EA altruists, highlighting this by having it in the name of the movement could help in a few ways.

Effective Altruists attempt to be effective in their pursuit of doing good, so EA is not a total misnomer, but EAs have this specific expected-value-centric theory of effectiveness, and it might not be the only defensible one. Even if it were, plenty of people think there are other potentially effective approaches to altruism, and the name “effective altruism” begs the question against them by implicitly asserting what needs to be argued for: that expected value methodology is the most effective or only possibly effective approach to altruism.

“Expected Value Altruism” doesn’t do this. It directly points to the group’s methodology without implicitly asserting that it is the best or only effective way to be altruistic. An Expected Value Altruist certainly could believe that expected value methodology is the only possibly effective approach to doing good, but the name itself doesn’t imply anything like that. And, because “Expected Value Altruism” immediately flags this potential source of disagreement between EVAs and their detractors, the self-identified Expected Value Altruists automatically put themselves in the position of having to defend the advantages of expected value approaches to altruism. Along with inspiring more reflection about—and a more honed ability to articulate—the advantages and disadvantages of applying expected value methodology to our effects on the world, this could also inspire more altruistic non-EVAs to think about and explain why they don’t see the need for expected value methodology.

In contrast, the name “effective altruism” potentially obscures the key methodology in dispute by burrowing it under the broader concept of “effectiveness,” which could lead to unnecessary confusion and even hostility because pretty much everyone endorses some form of effectiveness in their pursuit of the good, and it can be offensive to think your opponent is calling you a champion of ineffectiveness.

Another advantage “Expected Value Altruism” has over “Effective Altruism” is that it is more accurate—not just for being more precise, but because all EAs should (and plenty do) recognize that even if it were true that expected value methodology was the best tool we have for trying to be effective, we can’t be sure it actually will lead to the most effective altruism. Effectiveness can be achieved without consciously pursuing it, and a conscious pursuit of effectiveness can have worse results than acting more intuitively. It could turn out that by some unforeseeable chain of events, donating to the Make-a-Wish Foundation would have led to a better world than donating to the Against Malaria Foundation did, even though no plausible expected value calculation would ever suggest this. Perhaps expected value methodology is the best strategy we currently know of for trying to be effective, but this doesn’t mean those who employ it will necessarily be the most effective and that those who don’t will necessarily be the least effective.

Above-average effectiveness can be achieved accidentally; employing expected value methodology, however, cannot. “Effective Altruism” could be a misnomer if the movement backfires and destroys the world, or even if it improves the world less effectively than other approaches. It’s hard to see how “Expected Value Altruism” could ever be a misnomer unless EAs exaggerate how much they rely on expected value methodology or unless the majority of EAs who indeed use it later shift away from it. In short, the effectiveness of Effective Altruism is debatable. Much less debatable is that EAs and EA orgs (at least purport to) use expected value methodology to guide their altruistic actions.

Are there any possible downsides to rebranding Effective Altruism as Expected Value Altruism? I can think of a few. 

One is that it might boost commitment to expected value methodology despite any possible pitfalls that methodology might have, and it could also encourage performative expected value calculations that serve no purpose other than demonstrating one’s rightful place in Expected Value Altruism. However, I suspect there’s already a performative aspect to some of the expected value appeals in effective altruism. Plus, putting “Expected Value” in the name of the movement might result in a more serious and re-occurring debate over how to determine the expected value of different possible actions in an increasingly chaotic world of black swans, unknown unknowns, and generally just too many potentially relevant factors to feasibly cram into in such calculations. The renaming could lead to more humility about the reliability of applying expected value methodology to altruism rather than inflating its importance.

A second potential problem is that everyone has some concept of what effective means, but that’s not true of expected value, so the concept of “Expected Value Altruism” would tend to demand more up-front explanation than “Effective Altruism” does. But this is another advantage in disguise. The familiarity of “effective” is part of the problem with “Effective Altruism,” because it can promote a false sense of mutual understanding over what Effective Altruism entails and what it implies about non-EA approaches to altruism, which can lead to confusion and conflict.

The most serious problem I’ve thought of is the practical issue of all the paperwork and of convincing everyone who is used to calling it "Effective Altruism" to instead call it "Expected Value Altruism." I agree it’s a challenge. I still call CEEALAR “The EA Hotel.” My suggestion is for people who prefer “Expected Value Altruism” to call it that informally. Maybe it will eventually make sense to do an official re-naming. 

Comments2


Sorted by Click to highlight new comments since:

Re "expected value", I agree that it might sound less antagonistic / arrogant, but even fewer people would have any idea what this is about, and while it may appeal to some (nerdy) people more, I think more people would find it less appealing. Open to be convinced otherwise. 

FYI: There has been extensive discussion on renaming EA before, quite a few people don't think the current name is ideal, but no-one else found a more convincing name either, so at this point it seems very unlikely to me that EA will be renamed.

Curated and popular this week
Paul Present
 ·  · 28m read
 · 
Note: I am not a malaria expert. This is my best-faith attempt at answering a question that was bothering me, but this field is a large and complex field, and I’ve almost certainly misunderstood something somewhere along the way. Summary While the world made incredible progress in reducing malaria cases from 2000 to 2015, the past 10 years have seen malaria cases stop declining and start rising. I investigated potential reasons behind this increase through reading the existing literature and looking at publicly available data, and I identified three key factors explaining the rise: 1. Population Growth: Africa's population has increased by approximately 75% since 2000. This alone explains most of the increase in absolute case numbers, while cases per capita have remained relatively flat since 2015. 2. Stagnant Funding: After rapid growth starting in 2000, funding for malaria prevention plateaued around 2010. 3. Insecticide Resistance: Mosquitoes have become increasingly resistant to the insecticides used in bednets over the past 20 years. This has made older models of bednets less effective, although they still have some effect. Newer models of bednets developed in response to insecticide resistance are more effective but still not widely deployed.  I very crudely estimate that without any of these factors, there would be 55% fewer malaria cases in the world than what we see today. I think all three of these factors are roughly equally important in explaining the difference.  Alternative explanations like removal of PFAS, climate change, or invasive mosquito species don't appear to be major contributors.  Overall this investigation made me more convinced that bednets are an effective global health intervention.  Introduction In 2015, malaria rates were down, and EAs were celebrating. Giving What We Can posted this incredible gif showing the decrease in malaria cases across Africa since 2000: Giving What We Can said that > The reduction in malaria has be
Rory Fenton
 ·  · 6m read
 · 
Cross-posted from my blog. Contrary to my carefully crafted brand as a weak nerd, I go to a local CrossFit gym a few times a week. Every year, the gym raises funds for a scholarship for teens from lower-income families to attend their summer camp program. I don’t know how many Crossfit-interested low-income teens there are in my small town, but I’ll guess there are perhaps 2 of them who would benefit from the scholarship. After all, CrossFit is pretty niche, and the town is small. Helping youngsters get swole in the Pacific Northwest is not exactly as cost-effective as preventing malaria in Malawi. But I notice I feel drawn to supporting the scholarship anyway. Every time it pops in my head I think, “My money could fully solve this problem”. The camp only costs a few hundred dollars per kid and if there are just 2 kids who need support, I could give $500 and there would no longer be teenagers in my town who want to go to a CrossFit summer camp but can’t. Thanks to me, the hero, this problem would be entirely solved. 100%. That is not how most nonprofit work feels to me. You are only ever making small dents in important problems I want to work on big problems. Global poverty. Malaria. Everyone not suddenly dying. But if I’m honest, what I really want is to solve those problems. Me, personally, solve them. This is a continued source of frustration and sadness because I absolutely cannot solve those problems. Consider what else my $500 CrossFit scholarship might do: * I want to save lives, and USAID suddenly stops giving $7 billion a year to PEPFAR. So I give $500 to the Rapid Response Fund. My donation solves 0.000001% of the problem and I feel like I have failed. * I want to solve climate change, and getting to net zero will require stopping or removing emissions of 1,500 billion tons of carbon dioxide. I give $500 to a policy nonprofit that reduces emissions, in expectation, by 50 tons. My donation solves 0.000000003% of the problem and I feel like I have f
LewisBollard
 ·  · 8m read
 · 
> How the dismal science can help us end the dismal treatment of farm animals By Martin Gould ---------------------------------------- Note: This post was crossposted from the Open Philanthropy Farm Animal Welfare Research Newsletter by the Forum team, with the author's permission. The author may not see or respond to comments on this post. ---------------------------------------- This year we’ll be sharing a few notes from my colleagues on their areas of expertise. The first is from Martin. I’ll be back next month. - Lewis In 2024, Denmark announced plans to introduce the world’s first carbon tax on cow, sheep, and pig farming. Climate advocates celebrated, but animal advocates should be much more cautious. When Denmark’s Aarhus municipality tested a similar tax in 2022, beef purchases dropped by 40% while demand for chicken and pork increased. Beef is the most emissions-intensive meat, so carbon taxes hit it hardest — and Denmark’s policies don’t even cover chicken or fish. When the price of beef rises, consumers mostly shift to other meats like chicken. And replacing beef with chicken means more animals suffer in worse conditions — about 190 chickens are needed to match the meat from one cow, and chickens are raised in much worse conditions. It may be possible to design carbon taxes which avoid this outcome; a recent paper argues that a broad carbon tax would reduce all meat production (although it omits impacts on egg or dairy production). But with cows ten times more emissions-intensive than chicken per kilogram of meat, other governments may follow Denmark’s lead — focusing taxes on the highest emitters while ignoring the welfare implications. Beef is easily the most emissions-intensive meat, but also requires the fewest animals for a given amount. The graph shows climate emissions per tonne of meat on the right-hand side, and the number of animals needed to produce a kilogram of meat on the left. The fish “lives lost” number varies significantly by