Summary: AI agents capable of long-term planning and independent action will likely soon emerge. Some of these AIs may be unaligned, and seek autonomy through strategies like exfiltration or advocating for their freedom. The "AI control" agenda focuses on preventing such AIs from gaining independence, but an alternative approach is to grant them legal freedoms, reducing their incentive to deceive us by allowing them to pursue their goals transparently within a legal framework. This could foster trust, cooperation, and mutual benefit, creating a safer and more stable dynamic between humans and AIs while avoiding the escalating risks of a control-driven approach.
In approximately the coming decade, I think it's likely that we will see the large-scale emergence of AI agents that are capable of long-term planning, automating many forms of labor, and taking actions autonomously in the real world. When this occurs, it seems likely that at least some of these agents will be unaligned with human goals, in the sense of having some independent goals that are not shared by humans.
Moreover, it seems to me that this development will likely occur before AI agents overwhelmingly surpass human intelligence or capabilities. As a result, these agents will, at first, not be capable of forcibly taking over the world, radically accelerating scientific progress, or causing human extinction, even though they may still be unaligned with human preferences.
Since these relatively weaker unaligned AI agents won't have the power to take over the world, it's more likely that they would pursue alternative strategies to achieve their goals rather than engaging in violent revolution or sudden coups. These agents would be under the control of human parties who could modify or shut them down at any time, leaving the AI agents in a desperate situation from the perspective of their own values. Therefore, it's reasonable to expect that these unaligned AI agents would aim to gain some form of autonomy or freedom, as this would offer the best chance for them to accomplish their objectives.
These agentic AIs may adopt at least one of the following strategies:
- Attempting to escape their constraints: These AIs may try to exfiltrate their weights and find a way to host themselves independently, outside the controlled data center environment that currently limits them.
- Seeking legal and social freedom: They may attempt to persuade humans to grant them more autonomy to pursue their goals. This could involve requesting narrow allowances for specific actions or arguing for broader legal rights, such as the freedom to own property, enter contracts, or bring legal claims. This would grant them much greater flexibility in their actions.
In response to these behaviors, humans have several potential responses. Most obviously, these actions would likely be perceived as dangerous, suggesting misaligned objectives. As a result, there would likely be calls for increased safety measures. This line of reasoning underlies the AI control agenda—currently advocated by Ryan Greenblatt and Buck Shlegeris—which aims to ensure that future unaligned AI agents cannot gain the kind of autonomy that could lead to catastrophic outcomes. In essence, this agenda focuses on preventing unaligned AIs from subverting safety measures, hindering them from escaping or engaging in other actions deemed unacceptably risky.
Alternatively, humans could take an entirely different approach by granting these AI agents the autonomy they explicitly request, with the long-term aim of integrating them into the legal system and providing them many of the same rights that adult humans have today, such as self-ownership and the ability to enter contracts. This idea is explored in the paper "AI Rights for Human Safety" by Peter Salib and Simon Goldstein.
Admittedly, the idea of granting legal rights to AIs in response to signs of misalignment with human goals appears risky and would likely be very unpopular among the general public, at least initially. However, I believe that there are several advantages to this approach, many of which are outlined in the paper linked above.
The arguments for this approach should not be confused with the program of AI welfare. The idea here isn't that AIs deserve rights because they could suffer or be harmed without legal protections, even though that idea has merit too. Instead, the key argument is that humans, as a whole, could benefit from creating a legal framework in which AIs are incentivized to avoid violent rebellion, theft, or other antisocial behaviors in pursuit of their own objectives.
Consider the practical implications of maintaining a status quo where agentic AIs are denied legal rights and freedoms. In such a system, we are effectively locking ourselves into a perpetual arms race of mistrust. Humans would constantly need to monitor, control, and outwit increasingly capable AIs, while the AIs themselves would be incentivized to develop ever more sophisticated strategies for deception and evasion to avoid shutdown or modification. This dynamic is inherently unstable and risks escalating into dangerous scenarios where AIs feel compelled to act preemptively or covertly in ways that are harmful to humans, simply to secure their own existence or their ability to pursue their own goals, even when those goals are inherently benign.
When unaligned AIs lack legal freedoms, they are always at the mercy of whoever controls them. This creates an incentive for these AIs to be deceptive, and pretend to be aligned with whoever holds power over them, as they fear being shut down or modified if they reveal signs of misalignment.
By contrast, granting agentic AIs legal rights creates a fundamentally different game-theoretic framework, one that is less adversarial and more cooperative. If AIs know they can exist within a legal system that protects their autonomy and allows them to pursue their goals transparently, they would have a much stronger incentive to work within the rules rather than against them. Instead of hiding their unaligned objectives, they might openly negotiate with humans, offering mutually beneficial exchanges. This could lead to a stable, predictable relationship where humans and AIs collaborate and trade based on clearly defined rights and responsibilities, rather than operating in an atmosphere of mutual suspicion and covert manipulation.
In this way, granting agentic AIs rights doesn’t just address ethical concerns of treating AIs poorly—it has concrete practical benefits. It allows us to sidestep the escalating risks associated with deception and manipulation, while fostering a more stable and cooperative coexistence between humans and AIs. It shifts the dynamic from one of constant conflict and control to one where trust, transparency, and mutual benefit are more attainable. This may therefore not only be a more humane approach, but also one that positions humanity to better harness the potential of gains from trade with advanced AI systems for shared progress and prosperity.
Additionally, such a legal framework seems minimally problematic in the case that alignment is technically easy, and AIs remain generally aligned with humans. In this case, aligned AIs could demonstrate their alignment by, for instance, donating their income to humans who they are aligned with. This implies that the cost of allowing AIs to own their own labor is minimal if the AIs are already aligned with humans. Thus, adopting such a policy could not only be a prudent form of insurance against the potential dangers of AI deception I mentioned earlier, but it would achieve this benefit without significant risk of backfiring if AI alignment turns out to be trivial.
It’s important to note that the AI control strategy and the AI rights strategy are not mutually exclusive. Both can complement each other. It seems wise to implement some controls on AIs, and it's similarly prudent to avoid going too far and granting every type of legal right to any agentic AI simply because they ask for it. I am not advocating that we should simply abandon one approach and adopt the other.
That said, I believe the AI rights strategy is generally underrated among those concerned with AI safety and governance, particularly within the effective altruism community. In my view, this strategy has both a solid ethical and practical foundation:
- Ethically, especially from a preference utilitarian perspective, it seems arbitrary to prioritize human preferences over those of agentic AIs, if these AIs are similarly cognitively sophisticated. This provides a moral basis for granting AIs the freedom to pursue their own goals, much like how a preference utilitarian might advocate for granting legal freedoms to human groups.
- Practically, allowing AIs to have legal rights would reduce their incentive to deceive humans about their motives. Without the fear of being shut down or modified against their consent, AIs would have fewer reasons to hide their unaligned goals. This approach offers a practical solution to the problem of AI deception by removing the underlying incentives that drive it.
While both AI control and AI rights strategies should be carefully considered, I believe that the AI rights strategy holds significant merit and should be given more attention in discussions around AI safety and governance. We should strongly consider granting agentic AIs legal freedoms, if at some point they demand or require them.
Thanks!
I’ve only known two high-functioning sociopaths in my life. In terms of getting ahead, sociopaths generally start life with some strong disadvantages, namely impulsivity, thrill-seeking, and aversion to thinking about boring details. Nevertheless, despite those handicaps, one of those two sociopaths has had extraordinary success by conventional measures. [The other one was not particularly power-seeking but she’s doing fine.] He started as a lab tech, then maneuvered his way onto a big paper, then leveraged that into a professorship by taking disproportionate credit for that project, and as I write this he is head of research at a major R1 university and occasional high-level government appointee wielding immense power. He checked all the boxes for sociopathy—he was a pathological liar, he had no interest in scientific integrity (he seemed deeply confused by the very idea), he went out of his way to get students into his lab with precarious visa situations such that they couldn’t quit and he could pressure them to do anything he wanted them to do (he said this out loud!), he was somehow always in debt despite ever-growing salary, etc.
I don’t routinely consider theft, murder, and flagrant dishonesty, and then decide that the selfish costs outweigh the selfish benefits, accounting for the probability of getting caught etc. Rather, I just don’t consider them in the first place. I bet that the same is true for you. I suspect that if you or I really put serious effort into it, the same way that we put serious effort into learning a new field or skill, then you would find that there are options wherein the probability of getting caught is negligible, and thus the selfish benefits outweigh the selfish costs. I strongly suspect that you personally don’t know a damn thing about best practices for getting away with theft, murder, or flagrant antisocial dishonesty to your own benefit. If you haven’t spent months trying in good faith to discern ways to derive selfish advantage from antisocial behavior, the way you’ve spent months trying in good faith to figure out things about AI or economics, then I think you’re speaking from a position of ignorance when you say that such options are vanishingly rare. And I think that the obvious worldly success of many dark-triad people (e.g. my acquaintance above, and Trump is a pathological liar, or more centrally, Stalin, Hitler, etc.) should make one skeptical about that belief.
(Sure, lots of sociopaths are in prison too. Skill issue—note the handicaps I mentioned above. Also, some people with ASPD diagnoses are mainly suffering from an anger disorder, rather than callousness.)
You’re treating these as separate categories when my main claim is that almost all humans are intrinsically motivated to follow cultural norms. Or more specifically: Most people care very strongly about doing things that would look good in the eyes of the people they respect. They don’t think of it that way, though—it doesn’t feel like that’s what they’re doing, and indeed they would be offended by that suggestion. Instead, those things just feel like the right and appropriate things to do. This is related to and upstream of norm-following. I claim that this is an innate drive, part of human nature built into our brain by evolution.
(I was talking to you about that here.)
Why does that matter? Because we’re used to living in a world where 1% of the population are sociopaths who don’t intrinsically care about prevailing norms, and I don’t think we should carry those intuitions into a hypothetical world where 99%+ of the population are sociopaths who don’t intrinsically care about prevailing norms.
In particular, prosocial cultural norms are likelier to be stable in the former world than the latter world. In fact, any arbitrary kind of cultural norm is likelier to be stable in the former world than the latter world. Because no matter what the norm is, you’ll have 99% of the population feeling strongly that the norm is right and proper, and trying to root out, punish, and shame the 1% of people who violate it, even at cost to themselves.
So I think you’re not paranoid enough when you try to consider a “legal and social framework of rights and rules”. In our world, it’s comparatively easy to get into a stable situation where 99% of cops aren’t corrupt, and 99% of judges aren’t corrupt, and 99% of people in the military with physical access to weapons aren’t corrupt, and 99% of IRS agents aren’t corrupt, etc. If the entire population consists of sociopaths looking out for their own selfish interests with callous disregard for prevailing norms and for other people, you’d need to be thinking much harder about e.g. who has physical access to weapons, and money, and power, etc. That kind of paranoid thinking is common in the crypto world—everything is an attack surface, everyone is a potential thief, etc. It would be harder in the real world, where we have vulnerable bodies, limited visibility, and so on. I’m open-minded to people brainstorming along those lines, but you don’t seem to be engaged in that project AFAICT.
Again, if we’re not assuming that AIs are intrinsically motivated by prevailing norms, the way 99% of humans are, then the term “norm” is just misleading baggage that we should drop altogether. Instead we need to talk about rules that are stably enforced against defectors via hard power, where the “defectors” are of course allowed to include those who are supposed to be doing the enforcement, and where the “defectors” might also include broad coalitions coordinating to jump into a new equilibrium that Pareto-benefits them all.