Hide table of contents

I have not found any Effective Altruist literature on free will debates and implications, which I was surprised by as it seems to be a topic of potentially great moral importance.  Can anyone point me to existing work?

If free will doesn't exist, does that ruin/render void the EA endeavour?  If so are most EAs libertarians re free will?

In light of thinkers such as Sam Harris's work dismantling free will, which I find compelling, https://samharris.org/the-illusion-of-free-will/ and given the ought-implies-can principle, can morality be salvaged?  Eg, how could I 'ought' to choose an impactful career, if my actions are all predetermined?

16

0
0

Reactions

0
0
New Answer
New Comment


4 Answers sorted by

If skepticism about free will renders the EA endeavor void, then wouldn't it also render any action-guiding principles void (including principles about what's best to do out of self-interest)? In which case, it seems odd to single out its consequences for EA.

You sometimes see some (implicit) moving between "we did this good thing, but there's a sense in which we can't take credit, because it was determined before we chose to do it" to "we did this good thing, but there's a sense in which we can't take credit, because it would have happened whether or not we chose to do it", where the latter can be untrue even if the former always true. The former doesn't imply anything about what you should have done instead, while the latter does but has nothing to do with skepticism about free will. So even if determinism undermines certain kinds of "you ought to x" claims, it doesn't imply "you ought to not bother doing x" — it does not justify resignation. There is a parallel (though maybe more problematic) discussion about what to do about the possibility of nihilism.

Anyway, even skeptics about free will can agree that ex post it was good that the good thing happened (compared to it not happening), and they can agree that certain choices were instrumental in it happening (if the choices weren't made, it wouldn't have happened). Looking forward, the skeptic could also understand "you ought to x" claims as saying "the world where you do x will be better than the world where you don't, and I don't have enough information to know which world we're in". They also don't need to deny that people are and will continue to be sensitive to "ought" claims in the sense that explaining to people why they ought to do something can make them more likely to do it compared to the world where you don't explain why. Basically, counterfactual talk can still make sense for determinists. And all this seems like more then enough for anything worth caring about — I don't think any part of EA requires our choices to be undetermined or freely made in some especially deep way.

Some things you might be interested in reading —

I think maybe this free will stuff does matter in a more practical way when it comes to prison reform and punishment, since (plausibly) support for 'retributive' punishment vs rehabilitation comes from attitudes about free will and responsbility that are either incoherent or wrong in a influencable way. 

Thanks finm, I agree, EA is far from uniquely vulnerable to determinism, as you say all action-guiding principles would be affected, I was just contextualising to the forum.

Yes, I think that's a useful distinction, Harris labels these 'determinism' and 'fatalism' respectively, and so still believes our decisions matter in the sense that they will impact the value of future world-states.

That could work to reformulate the meaning of ought statements, though I still feel something important is lost from ethics if determinism is true.

Will have a look at the resources :)

According to the PhilPapers survey, over half of philosophers favour a compatibilist approach to free will - i.e. that free will is compatible with determinism.

I also recommend the LessWrong writing on the subject.

Thanks, I am quite sceptical of compatibilism as a work-around as it still seems unreasonable to say I ought to have done something I metaphysically could not have done.  But yes, given epistemic modesty I can't dismiss it entirely when so many professional philosophers support it.  I'll have a look through LessWrong.

“If free will doesn’t exist, does that ruin/render void the EA endeavor?”

 

Well, what does it matter if free will exists? Even if free will doesn’t exist, my life circumstances have led to me becoming invested in improving the world by engaging in altruism. My brain’s reward circuitry is still aligned with doing the most good that I can do for as long as I am able. I think for most of us who identify as altruists, the tendency to help those who need help is not tied to the idea of free will. I suppose that there are people who would take the absence of free will to be a pass to stray from altruism, but I doubt you’ll find them in the EA community.

 

Personally, losing my belief in free will has had a big, big difference in how I see the world. Because I believe free will doesn’t exist, I cease to judge those who are on the bottom rungs of our society. I have a deeper compassion for people who have addictions, who have committed crimes, who are not the easiest to care about. I have more patience with those who have differing opinions, even with flat-earthers and religious fundamentalists.

 

Shedding my belief in free will also helped me be kinder to myself. I am more patient whenever I face challenges arising from my shortcomings. I forgive myself for my failures and try to be humble even in my triumphs. My prime motivation to make the world a better place is no longer guilt but rather a genuine pleasure in spreading kindness. 

 

In so many different ways, not believing in free will has made me a better altruist and a kinder friend to myself. I hope questioning free will does the same to you!

Thanks for that personal perspective, good to hear.  For me too I think doubting free will is beneficial in my perceptions of others, as you say it makes judgementalism impossible.  I am yet to reconcile myself emotionally to me lacking freedom though, and perhaps never will.

Yes, perhaps some people will be demotivated by disbelieving free will and choose to be less altruistic, which itself is determined, as is how much I will try to break them out of it.  My moral system would take a lot of adjusting to without being able to use 'ought' statements (given ough-implies-can conception).

I'm no expert in this topic and haven't read Sam Harris's argument, but there are a couple of things I usually bear in mind:

1. If you're uncertain about whether determinism is true (that is, the probability you assign to hard determinism is less than 1), then it seems you should still act as though you are not determined.  Then we can apply reasoning like Pascal's Wager -- if determinism is false, then sadistic torture is terrible; if it's right, then we are indifferent.  Hence it seems that we should still act on the side of morality still having bearing.

2. A more compelling response (although, still contentious) is compatibilism.  I leave you to explore it here.

Exactly, 1 has been the approach I have taken; as long as I am unsure I err on the side of safety and believing in morally large universes including those with free will.  That said, it would be interesting if many EAs were similar and thought something like "there's only a ~10% chance free will and hence morality is real, so very likely my life is useless, but I am trying anyway".  I think that is a good approach, but would be an odd outcome.

Comments4
Sorted by Click to highlight new comments since:

If free will doesn't exist, does that ruin/render void the EA endeavour?

Can you say more about why free will not existing is relevant to morality? 

My personal take is that free will seems like a pretty meaningless and confused concept, and probably doesn't exist (whatever that means). But that I want to do what I can to make the world a better place anyway, in the same way that I clearly want and value things in my normal life, regardless of whether I'm doing this with free will.

Sure, I think that makes sense if we see EA as just another preference like any other, I think if we were 100% certain there was no free will though it would greatly reduce the moral force of the argument supporting EA (and any decision-guiding framework), as I couldn't reasonably tell someone or myself, 'you ought to do X over and above Y'.

As a strong free will sceptic I agree that you can never reasonably tell someone “you ought to do X over and above Y”.

However, it makes complete sense to me in a purely deterministic world to make one small addition to the phrase: “you ought to do X over and above Y in order to achieve Z”. The ought has no meaning without the Z, with the Z representing the ideal world you are deterministically programmed to want to live in.

Thanks for the comment (and welcome to the Forum! :) ). Yeah using conditional oughts seems like a pretty reasonable approach to me, though of course has some convenience cost when the Z is very widely shared ('you ought to fix your brakes over drive without brakes in order to not crash') so can perhaps then be implied.

Curated and popular this week
 ·  · 5m read
 · 
[Cross-posted from my Substack here] If you spend time with people trying to change the world, you’ll come to an interesting conundrum: Various advocacy groups reference previous successful social movements as to why their chosen strategy is the most important one. Yet, these groups often follow wildly different strategies from each other to achieve social change. So, which one of them is right? The answer is all of them and none of them. This is because many people use research and historical movements to justify their pre-existing beliefs about how social change happens. Simply, you can find a case study to fit most plausible theories of how social change happens. For example, the groups might say: * Repeated nonviolent disruption is the key to social change, citing the Freedom Riders from the civil rights Movement or Act Up! from the gay rights movement. * Technological progress is what drives improvements in the human condition if you consider the development of the contraceptive pill funded by Katharine McCormick. * Organising and base-building is how change happens, as inspired by Ella Baker, the NAACP or Cesar Chavez from the United Workers Movement. * Insider advocacy is the real secret of social movements – look no further than how influential the Leadership Conference on Civil Rights was in passing the Civil Rights Acts of 1960 & 1964. * Democratic participation is the backbone of social change – just look at how Ireland lifted a ban on abortion via a Citizen’s Assembly. * And so on… To paint this picture, we can see this in action below: Source: Just Stop Oil which focuses on…civil resistance and disruption Source: The Civic Power Fund which focuses on… local organising What do we take away from all this? In my mind, a few key things: 1. Many different approaches have worked in changing the world so we should be humble and not assume we are doing The Most Important Thing 2. The case studies we focus on are likely confirmation bias, where
 ·  · 2m read
 · 
I speak to many entrepreneurial people trying to do a large amount of good by starting a nonprofit organisation. I think this is often an error for four main reasons. 1. Scalability 2. Capital counterfactuals 3. Standards 4. Learning potential 5. Earning to give potential These arguments are most applicable to starting high-growth organisations, such as startups.[1] Scalability There is a lot of capital available for startups, and established mechanisms exist to continue raising funds if the ROI appears high. It seems extremely difficult to operate a nonprofit with a budget of more than $30M per year (e.g., with approximately 150 people), but this is not particularly unusual for for-profit organisations. Capital Counterfactuals I generally believe that value-aligned funders are spending their money reasonably well, while for-profit investors are spending theirs extremely poorly (on altruistic grounds). If you can redirect that funding towards high-altruism value work, you could potentially create a much larger delta between your use of funding and the counterfactual of someone else receiving those funds. You also won’t be reliant on constantly convincing donors to give you money, once you’re generating revenue. Standards Nonprofits have significantly weaker feedback mechanisms compared to for-profits. They are often difficult to evaluate and lack a natural kill function. Few people are going to complain that you provided bad service when it didn’t cost them anything. Most nonprofits are not very ambitious, despite having large moral ambitions. It’s challenging to find talented people willing to accept a substantial pay cut to work with you. For-profits are considerably more likely to create something that people actually want. Learning Potential Most people should be trying to put themselves in a better position to do useful work later on. People often report learning a great deal from working at high-growth companies, building interesting connection
 ·  · 31m read
 · 
James Özden and Sam Glover at Social Change Lab wrote a literature review on protest outcomes[1] as part of a broader investigation[2] on protest effectiveness. The report covers multiple lines of evidence and addresses many relevant questions, but does not say much about the methodological quality of the research. So that's what I'm going to do today. I reviewed the evidence on protest outcomes, focusing only on the highest-quality research, to answer two questions: 1. Do protests work? 2. Are Social Change Lab's conclusions consistent with the highest-quality evidence? Here's what I found: Do protests work? Highly likely (credence: 90%) in certain contexts, although it's unclear how well the results generalize. [More] Are Social Change Lab's conclusions consistent with the highest-quality evidence? Yes—the report's core claims are well-supported, although it overstates the strength of some of the evidence. [More] Cross-posted from my website. Introduction This article serves two purposes: First, it analyzes the evidence on protest outcomes. Second, it critically reviews the Social Change Lab literature review. Social Change Lab is not the only group that has reviewed protest effectiveness. I was able to find four literature reviews: 1. Animal Charity Evaluators (2018), Protest Intervention Report. 2. Orazani et al. (2021), Social movement strategy (nonviolent vs. violent) and the garnering of third-party support: A meta-analysis. 3. Social Change Lab – Ozden & Glover (2022), Literature Review: Protest Outcomes. 4. Shuman et al. (2024), When Are Social Protests Effective? The Animal Charity Evaluators review did not include many studies, and did not cite any natural experiments (only one had been published as of 2018). Orazani et al. (2021)[3] is a nice meta-analysis—it finds that when you show people news articles about nonviolent protests, they are more likely to express support for the protesters' cause. But what people say in a lab setting mig