Hide table of contents

I recently realized that saving money to build reasonable wealth is a priority in my life that I want to pursue alongside giving significantly. I want to feel independence from the need to work in my current job, be confident about buying a house for a family someday, be in a position to help family in need etc.

Saving and giving are two pots I would like to balance out. I am currently completely unsure about how much I should reasonably save and how much savings I need to reach my goals. 

Can you recommend resources, rules of thumb that you follow etc. to find my personally right saving rate?

Having that sorted would make me feel much more secure about my giving.

16

0
0
1

Reactions

0
0
1
New Answer
New Comment


3 Answers sorted by

I don't have this fully worked out for myself yet, but here are some things I've been considering recently. They're not exactly novel but might be helpful nonetheless.

1) Not having runway/savings has been really quite stressful/ inconvenient at times. I think there is some amount that does just seem robustly good to have. I don't have a clear idea of exactly how much that is though. Maybe thinking through the specific scenarios that have either happened or I'm worried might happen may point me in the right direction of a figure. 

 2) I've really noticed the hedonic treadmill now that I (and my friends) earn a salary. I also expect the pressure to use money for things other than donating to only increase as I get older (more responsibilities, unexpected life events, social pressure etc.).  By donating now, at the same time as I'm trying to build up savings, I feel like I'm locking it in as part of my identity and habits, rather than waiting and trusting a future me to donate, when in the future my goals might change. 

3) For me at least, it doesn't feel like I'm only weighing up savings and donating, it feels more like I'm weighing up 
- donating (you could say ~investing in my values)
- investing financially in my future (savings)
- investing in other ways in my future (eg. getting fit, eating well, going to therapy, taking care of important relationships, trying to have experiences that help me grow and learn). 

3) There is a chance though that money is disproportionately more useful sooner for the 3rd category - eg. getting help for (mental) health issues before they get worse, acquiring skills you can then use for longer, being able to do experiments that help you make life decisions. However, the benefit of acting sooner likely applies to savings and donating too, so I'm not too sure how to weigh them up. 

4) If you're waiting to donate while you build up savings, (or invest in other ways) I'd consider having a specific set goal/plan in advance. I have a (non-EA) friend to whom saving is really important. No matter how much he saves, though, it never feels 'enough' and he keeps moving his goalpost.

5) If I really sit with it, most of the things I think I need, I really don't, but giving them all up would likely make me very sad. On the margin, however, I absolutely could (and should by my values) give more. Elliot recently wrote "Do what you can. No more. No less". I personally need to do a big sit down and think hard about where the no more, no less, truly lands me. 
 

I'm not sure I have an answer, but one thing I aim to do is save a good amount and enable charitable donations of 10% or more by keeping housing and other fixed costs lower than I could, rather than seeing my budget as just a tradeoff between giving and saving.

I completely agree, using less money in our everyday lives is a huge Factor here which can easily be ignored. I also ask people to consider their generational wealth. Many people are set to inherit a lot of money with high likelihood but don't factor that into their saving/giving plans which seems weird to me at least with an EA framework. For example If we have a 80 percent chance of inheriting 500,000 Dollars then you can afford to save a lot less than someone who won't inherit anything.

As a side note personally I find saving very much money quite hard to justify morally, especially if you have a solid safety net with government/family/friends but that's a whole nother discussion!

3
MaciekZajac
Just a minor point - i I am willing to rely on family/friends as my financial safety net, then I should also be ready to reciprocate this to an equal degree. Relying on each other for financial safety does not obviate the need for saving, on the contrary, it necessitates them. Not saving and risking having to rely on a government safety net, while defensible, is not wholly unproblematic - surely this is not a universalizable strategy.
2
NickLaing
That's a fair point, except I think it is universalisable to some extent because risk is pooled and only a few in the rich Western world will undergo catastrophic issues. Also there's some argument that it doesn't need to be universal, because we are active at the margins - others are going to save lots regardless but maybe we don't need to? I agree it's complicated.
3
MaciekZajac
I suppose this would depend on the specifics of the society one lives in - is the social safety net rarely used and not under strain because everybody is generally prosperous and it exists just in case? Or is it already strained and failing to catch some? At least in the latter case EAs making risky choices and ending up putting avoidable pressures on the social safety net would come at a direct cost to underprivileged individuals, kinda like flower-children relying on free neighborhoods clinics in the 60's ended up hurting local community access to basic healthcare. I'm also skeptical by default o any EA exceptionalism - I donate much so I am allowed to offload risks onto society could become "I donate much so I never tip/settle small debts/generally freeride in minor ways whenever I can". For me the strength of the basic EA pitch has always been its universalizability and full compatibility with otherwise respectable, responsible, others-friendly lifestyle.
2
NickLaing
Yeah I'm really talking about the situation where the safety net is rarely used bbecause everyone is generally prospeous. I suspect that's the situation even for the majority of the people here on the forum. Not people who don't have that kind of social capital in beind them I don't love the "risky" language. Risk goes in both directions. When people save a lot of moneym that risks the money doing nothing or just getting used to minimally improve a rich persons life. You might describe this as "safe", but I think it "risks" a whole lot of people dying in low income countries, or chickens remaining in a factory farm, or misaligned AI taking over because money sat in a bank rather than being spent in a better way. In these cases I prefer the language of "trade-off" rather than risk - we're taking risks/trade-offs with our money no matter what we do. I wouldn't advocate this in the "general EA pitch" or on the GWWCV website, but this might be useful for those of us who are really trying to really optimise what we do with our money.  I don't think the flower children in the 60s is a great para;;e;, because what they are doing is a definite drain on the safety net, not a slight chance like I'm talking about. Also your example talks about a situation where the resources are really finite.  I would also ask whether it is really that much of a "drain" on anyone? If excess money is sitting around in bank accounts, then I draw on it after losing my eyesight and need that money to support my life there's a decent chance no-one is really that much worse off. Not to be glib, but maybe someone buys a slightly smaller house, or goes on a couple less holidays and that's the worst of it. What I really don't like about the individualistic savings norms of today (in high income people) is close-to-zero pooling of risk - everyone saves their own money in case of a rainy day which doesn't happen to 95% of people, and the rest becomes increased generational wealth or gets spent on m
9
MaciekZajac
I see your point about the 'risk' language. I think the matter depends on whether/to what extent you find EA contributions to be a matter of universal duty. The more you view them this way, the less speaking about 'risk' here makes sense. This, however, is not a given - even if I myself feel morally bound to contribute to a certain extent, I may not believe others around me have such duties (the duty may derive from the promises I made, my attachment to consistency of my views etc.) And in that latter case obliging them to help me because I sacrificed my savings or the good cause seems not ok. Pooling of risk as you view it would require forming some kind of non-profit insurance entity that would still need to be well-organized/chartered and come with some operating costs. May be worth contemplating for the community as a venture, especially as its charter could include a mechanism for the money being automatically donated when certain risks do not materialize for the contributors.
2
NickLaing
Yep I love all this. Some intentional communities have this kind of insurance entity and it works OK. Like you say the amount of goodwill, honesty and trust needed for it to work is pretty large.
Curated and popular this week
 ·  · 11m read
 · 
Does a food carbon tax increase animal deaths and/or the total time of suffering of cows, pigs, chickens, and fish? Theoretically, this is possible, as a carbon tax could lead consumers to substitute, for example, beef with chicken. However, this is not per se the case, as animal products are not perfect substitutes.  I'm presenting the results of my master's thesis in Environmental Economics, which I re-worked and published on SSRN as a pre-print. My thesis develops a model of animal product substitution after a carbon tax, slaughter tax, and a meat tax. When I calibrate[1] this model for the U.S., there is a decrease in animal deaths and duration of suffering following a carbon tax. This suggests that a carbon tax can reduce animal suffering. Key points * Some animal products are carbon-intensive, like beef, but causes relatively few animal deaths or total time of suffering because the animals are large. Other animal products, like chicken, causes relatively many animal deaths or total time of suffering because the animals are small, but cause relatively low greenhouse gas emissions. * A carbon tax will make some animal products, like beef, much more expensive. As a result, people may buy more chicken. This would increase animal suffering, assuming that farm animals suffer. However, this is not per se the case. It is also possible that the direct negative effect of a carbon tax on chicken consumption is stronger than the indirect (positive) substitution effect from carbon-intensive products to chicken. * I developed a non-linear market model to predict the consumption of different animal products after a tax, based on own-price and cross-price elasticities. * When calibrated for the United States, this model predicts a decrease in the consumption of all animal products considered (beef, chicken, pork, and farmed fish). Therefore, the modelled carbon tax is actually good for animal welfare, assuming that animals live net-negative lives. * A slaughter tax (a
MarieF🔸
 ·  · 4m read
 · 
Summary * After >2 years at Hi-Med, I have decided to step down from my role. * This allows me to complete my medical residency for long-term career resilience, whilst still allowing part-time flexibility for direct charity work. It also allows me to donate more again. * Hi-Med is now looking to appoint its next Executive Director; the application deadline is 26 January 2025. * I will join Hi-Med’s governing board once we have appointed the next Executive Director. Before the role When I graduated from medical school in 2017, I had already started to give 10% of my income to effective charities, but I was unsure as to how I could best use my medical degree to make this world a better place. After dipping my toe into nonprofit fundraising (with Doctors Without Borders) and working in a medical career-related start-up to upskill, a talk given by Dixon Chibanda at EAG London 2018 deeply inspired me. I formed a rough plan to later found an organisation that would teach Post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD)-specific psychotherapeutic techniques to lay people to make evidence-based treatment of PTSD scalable. I started my medical residency in psychosomatic medicine in 2019, working for a specialised clinic for PTSD treatment until 2021, then rotated to child and adolescent psychiatry for a year and was half a year into the continuation of my specialisation training at a third hospital, when Akhil Bansal, whom I met at a recent EAG in London, reached out and encouraged me to apply for the ED position at Hi-Med - an organisation that I knew through my participation in their introductory fellowship (an academic paper about the outcomes of this first cohort can be found here). I seized the opportunity, applied, was offered the position, and started working full-time in November 2022.  During the role I feel truly privileged to have had the opportunity to lead High Impact Medicine for the past two years. My learning curve was steep - there were so many new things to
 ·  · 2m read
 · 
I can’t recall the last time I read a book in one sitting, but that’s what happened with Moral Ambition by bestselling author Rutger Bregman. I read the German edition, though it’s also available in Dutch (see James Herbert's Quick Take). An English release is slated for May. The book opens with the statement: “The greatest waste of our times is the waste of talent.” From there, Bregman builds a compelling case for privileged individuals to leave their “bullshit jobs” and tackle the world’s most pressing challenges. He weaves together narratives spanning historical movements like abolitionism, suffrage, and civil rights through to contemporary initiatives such as Against Malaria Foundation, Charity Entrepreneurship, LEEP, and the Shrimp Welfare Project. If you’ve been engaged with EA ideas, much of this will sound familiar, but I initially didn’t expect to enjoy the book as much as I did. However, Bregman’s skill as a storyteller and his knack for balancing theory and narrative make Moral Ambition a fascinating read. He reframes EA concepts in a more accessible way, such as replacing “counterfactuals” with the sports acronym “VORP” (Value Over Replacement Player). His use of stories and examples, paired with over 500 footnotes for details, makes the book approachable without sacrificing depth. I had some initial reservations. The book draws heavily on examples from the EA community but rarely engages directly with the movement, mentioning EA mainly in the context of FTX. The final chapter also promotes Bregman’s own initiative, The School for Moral Ambition. However, the school’s values closely align with core EA principles. The ITN framework and pitches for major EA cause areas are in the book, albeit with varying levels of depth. Having finished the book, I can appreciate its approach. Moral Ambition feels like a more pragmatic, less theory-heavy version of EA. The School for Moral Ambition has attracted better-known figures in Germany, such as the political e